HPS 0410 | Einstein for Everyone |
Back to main course page
John
D. Norton
Department of History and Philosophy of Science
University of Pittsburgh
Special relativity has changed our understanding of the nature of space, time, energy and other physical quantities. There is a very widespread feeling that the advent of special relativity has somehow changed the way we look at things in a sense that goes beyond these narrow physical results. What might that sense be?
The problem in answering is that there is scarcely a viewpoint or movement in modern philosophical thought that does not claim support in one way or another from Einstein's achievement. Clearly they cannot all be right. Quite often radically opposed viewpoints claim support from Einstein's achievement. In the end it is up to you to decide, since the issue remains controversial. You should use your knowledge of Einstein's theory and the circumstances surrounding its emergence to assist you.
Deciding what this significance might be is a
philosophical problem of no small interest. It must be resolved by the standard
methods of philosophical analysis. These methods are simple to
describe and not so difficult to learn. To begin, we need to keep two
notions in mind:
Critical analysis of the positions laid out then
merely consists in checking that each of these
elements is implemented properly. We would check that the thesis is
clearly formulated. We could check that the premises of the
arguments used are true. We would check that the steps of the
arguments are valid; that is, that they conform to the canons of
good reasoning. These requirement concerning thesis and argument are easy to state and look rather simple to satisfy. That is true as long as the problems dealt with are themselves easy. However once we start to entertain the traditionally intractable problems of philosophy, holding to them can be come quite demanding. Success at it may be a significant achievement and the best work in philosophy is distinguished by its success in holding to them in adverse circumstances. |
What is meant by "logic forces"? I just mean that
the inference from X, Y and Z to C is a valid argument, where
"argument" means what it means in any introductory logic class. If
you haven't had such a class, you should. It will help you clarify
your thinking a great deal. There you will learn than an argument is
not a shouting match. It is a sequence
of propositions. A valid argument is one in which each
proposition of the sequence is either introduced as a premise or
inferred from propositions earlier in the sequence. A valid deductive argument is one in which the truth of the premises necessitates the truth of conclusions inferred. For example: 1. All men are mortal. (Premise) 2. Socrates is a man. (Premise) 3. Socrates is mortal. (Inferred from 1.,2.) is a valid argument since, if premises 1. and 2. are true, then the conclusion 3. must also be true. A valid inductive argument is one in which the truth of the premises make the conclusion very likely to be true (or, sometimes, merely lend support to the truth of the conclusion). For example: 1. Most elephants are gray. (Premise) 2. Jumbo is an elephant. (Premise) 3. Jumbo is gray. (Inferred inductively from 1., 2.) is a valid inductive argument. |
Our goal is to take something that is puzzling, vague and elusive and make it precise and definite. If we do it right, the resolution of the puzzle should seem so straightforward that we wonder why it ever seemed otherwise.
The obvious candidate is just the basic content of the theory itself. It tells us some pretty surprising things about space and time and the matter they contain: that c is a fundamental barrier to all motions; that moving clocks slow; that simultaneity is relative; that energy and mass are equivalent; and so on. In so far as a perennial problem of philosophy has been to discern the nature of space and time, this is a reasonable answer. However it is usually thought that the advent of relativity somehow changed something fundamental, perhaps in how we see ourselves in the universe, or, more narrowly, in how we conduct our scientific investigations of that universe. Our quest is for morals of that type.
This and the next two chapters will describe some candidate morals of this broader type. I will give you my reaction to them to give you an example of how these claims may be analyzed and also to let you know what I think. Do you agree? Make up your own mind and you proceed. Your decision will be reported in the assignment.
This chapter will develop skeptical morals.
Einstein has shown us that the fundamental quantities
of physics are relative. Is this not a quite general moral? Is not what
is true or false or what is right or wrong relative to the individual?
Should we not say "Everything is relative"?
Here's the thesis and argument reconstructed:
Thesis: Everything is relative. There
are no absolute truths or absolutes of moral rectitude.
Argument:
1. All quantities in relativity theory have a meaning only relative to an
inertial frame or to an inertially moving observer. (Premise)
2. Relativity theory revealed that we were mistaken in our earlier belief
in absolute quantities in physics. (Premise)
3. Other notions (truth, moral rectitude) are like the quantities of
physics.
4. The lesson of relativity theory can be applied elsewhere. (1., 2., 3.,
by analogy)
5. Everything is relative. There are no absolute truths or absolutes of
moral rectitude. (From 1., 2., 3.)
Reconstructing the argument explicitly is already pretty damning. One sees that the moral is poorly drawn. Although it is obvious, let us spell out why.
First, the argument
is invalid. It seeks to use an argument by analogy. (This is like
that in some aspects; therefore this is like that in other aspects.)
The analogy fails. That certain quantities in relativity theory are
relative to the observer or, better said, state of motion of the observer,
has no real bearing on whether there is one
absolute standard for truth or for what is good or morally right. The same
word--relativism--is used in all cases, but the similarity of meaning is
so superficial as not to allow success in one domain to carry to another.
Second, the first premise is false. It is not true in relativity theory that "everything is relative." Only certain quantities are, albeit more than in classical physics. Some quantities are not relative. The simplest examples are the so-called "rest" quantities: rest mass, rest length etc. These are by definition the masses and lengths measured by a co-moving observer. They are characteristic properties of bodies and are of fundamental physical importance; (obviously) all observers must agree on their values. They are an absolute.
It is something of an accident of history to do with Einstein's way of thinking about relativity theory that we stress the "relative" aspect of the theory. In the more mathematical approach to the theory, what draws most attention is what is not relative, the so-called "invariants." So early in the history Einstein agreed with the great mathematician Felix Klein that a better name for the theory would have been "theory of invariants." |
Working in that mathematical tradition, Hermann
Minkowski, who introduced the notion of spacetime, wrote in his 1908
lecture "Space and Time": "...the word[s] relativity-postulate for the requirement of an invariance with the group Gc seem to me feeble. Since the postulate comes to mean that only the four-dimensional world in space and time is given by phenomena, but that the projection in space and in time may still be undertaken with a certain degree of freedom, I prefer to call it the postulate of the absolute world (or briefly the world-postulate)." |
Had history paid more attention to Minkowski's advocacy of the absolute world, might I now be lamenting the fallacy of inferring that "everything is absolute" from Einstein's theory?!
Here are the defects of the argument, displayed in compact form:
Thesis: Everything is relative. There
are no absolute truths or absolutes of moral rectitude.
Argument:
1. All quantities in
relativity theory have a meaning only relative to an inertial frame or
to an inertially moving observer. (Premise)
False premise: only some quantities in
relativity theory have a relative meaning.
2. Relativity theory revealed that we were mistaken in our earlier belief
in absolute quantities in physics. (Premise)
3. Other notions (truth, moral rightness) are like the quantities of
physics.
4. The lesson of relativity
theory can be applied elsewhere. There are no absolute truths or
absolutes of moral rectitude.(1., 2., 3., by analogy)
Fallacy: the analogy is too weak to
support the inference.
5. Everything is relative.
There are no absolute truths or absolutes of moral rectitude.(From 1.,
2., 3.)
Conclusion improperly drawn.
Relativity shows us that we cannot expect our common sense ideas about the physical world to be reliable.
Here is a reconstruction in terms of thesis and argument.
Thesis: Common sense is an unreliable
guide to truth.
Argument:
1. If common sense is a reliable guide to truth, then it will not assure
us of falsehoods. (Premise)
2. Common sense assures us that well-made rods and clocks are unaffected
by their motion. (Premise)
3. Relativity tells us that well-made rods and clocks shrink and slow when
they are moving. (Premise)
4. Common sense assures us of falsehoods. (From 2., 3.)
5. Common sense is not a reliable guide to the truth. (From 1., 4.)
On its face, this is acceptable. This claim is clear enough. The argument employs true premises and valid inferences. Informally, we had commonsense ideas about rods, clocks, simultaneity and more. We believed them because they seemed, well, commonsensical. Relativity showed that they were incorrect. Therefore commonsense ideas are untrustworthy, or at least on some occasions.
While the thesis and argument are acceptable, the view is oversimplified and the oversimplification is misleading.
It suggests that we needed relativity theory to tell us that common sense is unreliable. Anyone who has ever attended to developments in science will find numerous examples of science revealing the fragility of commonsense ideas. Copernicus did just that to our commonsense idea that we are at rest; he showed that we hurl through space at great speed in space, spinning all the while.
More seriously, the implicit assumption is that science and common sense are opposed. That is, they are two distinct ways that we know about the world. They are not distinct. There is an important connection between scientific breakthroughs and common sense.
Here's a list of things that we know through commonsense:
The sky
cannot fall down.
Cows cannot jump over the moon.
The earth is spherical.
People venturing to the other side will not fall off.
The earth spins on its axis and orbits the sun.
Matter is made of atoms too small to see.
Nothing goes faster than light.
The items of the list become successively more sophisticated. Indeed inspecting them reveals that each item of today's commonsense is a major result of yesterday's science.
What this suggests is that there is no independent notion of a common sense idea that somehow sits outside what we know through systematic investigations. Rather commonsense is a by-product of those investigation. The broad acceptance of common sense ideas about our physical world is merely the final stage of absorption of the results of scientific investigation. That is why today's common sense is yesterday's scientific breakthrough.
From this we can infer a more subtle moral: there is a kind of reliability in common sense ideas since they are ultimately, though indirectly, grounded in something more solid. Rather than needing a blanket skepticism about common sense ideas, the real thing to guard against is common sense that does not keep pace with newer investigations.
This file comes from Wellcome Images, a
website operated by Wellcome Trust, a global charitable foundation based
in the United Kingdom.
https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:An_allegory_of_malaria._Reproduction_of_an_engraving_after_M_Wellcome_V0010519.jpg
For example, it still seems to be a part of common sense that "airs" can be good for you. Don't we know of the benefits of clear mountain air? Similarly the wrong "airs" were thought to be unhealthy. The disease of malaria--literally "bad air" mal aria--was thought to be caused by them. Of course we now know that malaria is really caused by infection from mosquito borne parasites with the mosquitoes coming from swamps that might also emit bad smells. So the idea of avoiding bad smelling places to avoid the disease was right, but only indirectly.
Now let us return to the original argument to see how it should be adjusted. What we now see is that the first premise is misleading us. It says
1. If common sense is a reliable guide to truth, then it will not assure us of falsehoods. (Premise)
The ambiguity lies in "reliable." If we take "reliable" to mean "infallible" then the argument goes through.
Thesis: Common sense is not an infallible
guide to truth.
Argument:
1. If common sense is an infallible guide to truth, then
it will not assure us of falsehoods. (Premise)
2. Common sense assures us that well-made rods and clocks are unaffected
by their motion. (Premise)
3. Relativity tells us that well-made rods and clocks shrink and slow when
they are moving. (Premise)
4. Common sense assures us of falsehoods. (From 2., 3.)
5. Common sense is not an infallible guide to the truth.
(From 1., 4.)
This is what the argument really establishes. Expressed this way, we see that the original presentation of the argument led us to accept an unreasonably high standard of reliability. We would likely be quite happy to require only "generally reliable, but occasionally in error." With that more modest reading of "reliable," the argument no longer gives us such a strongly skeptical conclusion.
With the weaker sense of "reliable," the first premise becomes:
1. If common sense is a guide to truth that is generally
reliable, but occasionally in error, then it will not assure us
of falsehoods. (Premise)
False premise.
The premise is false since under the weaker sense of reliability, common sense is permitted an occasional error. We can no longer proceed to the skeptical conclusion of 5.
Relativity shows us that even the best of our
theories--classical mechanics--are unreliable. Why should we believe any
of the theories of modern science? Should we not expect the Einsteins of
tomorrow to overturn them all?
Alchemist searching for the philosopher's
stone that will convert base metals into gold.
Here is a reconstruction of the thesis and argument:
Thesis: All present scientific theories
are false.
Argument:
1. Relativity theory showed that classical Newtonian physics, an
apparently secure theory, was false. (Premise)
2. This refutation is common: many apparently secure theories have
subsequently been overturned by later theories. (Premise)
3. We should expect this pattern to continue, if we persist in seeking new
theories. (Premise)
4. Our best scientific theories will eventually be overturned by new
theories, if we persist in seeking new theories. (From 1., 2., 3.)
5. All present scientific theories are false. (From 4.)
The thesis is clear. The argument is also clear.
Relativity is just the latest of many
instances of new science overturning old theories we thought secure. So we
should expect our latest theories will eventually also be overturned, so
don't believe them.
In my view this is a lamentable argument, defective
because it rests on false premises. Both 1.
and 2. are false. Relativity theory did not wipe away all the physics that
went before. The bulk of that physics stays intact. Classical physics only
needs relativistic corrections when we deal with velocities close to the
speed of light. In virtually all applications, from designing bridges to
launching Apollo astronauts, classical physics suffices. Premise 2. fails
in the same way for other sciences.
The real pattern is that, once a science reaches some level of maturity, it becomes a fixture in the domains in which it was developed. The much publicized revolutions that eventually do arise supply adjustments outside of those domains. Here are some examples:
Science | Maturity achieved | Where it eventually fails |
Geometry | Ancient Greece, Euclid 3rd century BC | On cosmic scales |
Solar system astronomy | Heliocentrism, Copernicus, Kepler, 16th and 17th century | Very precise measurements correct their predictions but leave the heliocentric layout intact. |
Dynamics | Newtonian mechanics, 17th century | Domains of very fast (special relativity) very heavy (general relativity) very large (relativistic cosmology) very small (quantum theory) |
There is a much more benign moral in all this: do not trust theories in domains remote from those in which they were devised. The persistence of the skeptical argument is a puzzle to me. It simply rests on defective history of science, yet it remains popular among many historians of science who should know better.
Here is how the argument looks if we replace the false premises with true premises:
Thesis:
All present scientific theories are false.
Thesis: All present theories should not be trusted in
domains remote from those in which they were devised.
Argument:
1. Relativity theory showed
that classical Newtonian physics, an apparently secure theory, was
false. (Premise)
1. Relativity theory showed that classical Newtonian physics, an
apparently secure theory, was false in a domain remote from the one in
which it was devised. (Premise)
2. This refutation is common:
many apparently secure theories have subsequently been overturned by
later theories. (Premise)
2. This correction is common: many apparently secure theories have
subsequently been shown to fail in domains remote from the ones in which
they were devised. (Premise)
3. We should expect this pattern to continue, if we persist in seeking new
theories. (Premise)
4. Our best scientific theories will eventually be overturned
corrected by new theories, if we persist in seeking new theories. (From
1., 2., 3.)
5. All present scientific
theories are false. (From 4.)
5. All present theories should not be trusted in domains remote
from those in which they were devised.
In the two chapters following, we will see more candidate
morals described and analysed. The morals will not be displayed formally
in terms of thesis and argument, as was done above. You should, however,
remember that they are all to be held to the same standards of clarity of
expression and cogency of argument. If thinking about them becomes
troublesome, you should revert to the standard
philosopher's questions:
What is the thesis? What is the argument?
Copyright John D. Norton. February 2001;
October 2002; July 2006; February 2, 13, September, 23, 2008; February
1, 2010; February 10, 2013; February 4, 2015. February 6, 2016.