Theorem (Frobenius) - Berliner Sitzungsberichte, 1895, p. 984
If n divides the order of a group, then the number of elements in the
group whose orders divide n is a multiple of n.
Proof: Let G be a group of smallest order g for which the Theorem
fails. By this assumption the Theorem is true for all
groups H with
We call G a minimal counterexample. We
proceed to contradict the minimality of G, and thus conclude
that such G, in fact, does not exist.
For the group G, let n be the largest factor of g for which the
Theorem fails. Since the Theorem is clearly true for
n=1 and n=g, it follows that
1<n<g. Let Nm denote the number of elements
in G whose order divides m. Furthermore, let p be a prime which
divides g. We have
where Nn' denotes the number of elements in G whose order divides
np but not n. We aim to show that
Since by the
inductive assumption
and therefore
we conclude the
proof if we show that
then n divides the difference
Nnp-Nn'=Nn.
Let
order of x divides np but does not divide ;
Write
with (p,s)=1, that is, p and s are relatively prime.
Observe that if
then
divides the order of x. To show that
divides
we first show that
divides
then
show that s divides
(Note also that if
we are done.)
1. Let
Then all the
generators of
<y1> are in A; denote this set by A1. Select
Again there are
generators of <y2>, all of
them in A; call this set A2. Note that
,
for if
then
<y1>=<y>=<y2>, a contradiction. Since A is finite we have
(disjoint union), and since
divides Ai for all i, we
conclude that
divides
and hence
divides
2. (a) If
then x can be written uniquely as x=yz,
with y and z commuting and
and
Indeed, the cyclic
group <x> can be written as a direct sum <x>=YZ, where Y is
a subgroup of <x> of order
and Z is a subgroup of <x> of
order t. Thus x=yz, with
and ,
as stated. Furthermore,
since y and z are in <x>, they are both powers of x.
As to uniqueness, if x=yz, with y and z as above, then
Since
we conclude that
<y,z>=<x>. Thus y and z are in <x> and uniqueness follows from
the internal direct sum decomposition of
<x>=<y><z>. We call y
the
p-constituent of x.
(b) For
with
let
is the p-constituent of
Note that if y1 and y2 are two distinct elements of order
in
A, then
indeed, this follows from the uniqueness
of the p-constituent established in (a) above. We can now conclude
that the subsets Cy partition A.
(c) Let
Denote by Ky the centralizer of y in G.
Clearly
Let
and let
d=gcd(r,s), that is, d is the greatest
common divisor of r and s. Since r<g, by the inductive assumption
there exist a
multiple of d, say cd, elements in Ky/<y> whose orders divide d.
Let
be such a coset of <y> in Ky. We can represent
in the
form z<y>, with
a divisor of d.
[Indeed,
,
and therefore
z1t=yi, for some i. We seek j such that z=z1yj
satisfies
1=zt=z1tyjt=yiyjt=yi+jt. Since
such a j
exists; take
j=-it-1 (mod
]
Then
Each element of
Ky/<y> whose order divides d produces in this manner an element
of Cy. Thus
(d) Consider
the disjoint union taken over all the conjugates
of y in G. We assert that s divides
We have
.
Since g is divisible by s and r, it
follows that gd is divisible by rs. Hence s is a divisor of
Since
s and
are relatively prime, s must also be a factor of
.
In view of (b) above, this shows that s divides
This ends the proof.
By making use of the Möbius function we can obtain an expression
for the number of elements whose order is exactly n in terms of the
number of elements whose orders divide the divisors d of n.
Specifically, denote by f(d) the number of elements whose orders are
exactly n. Let h(d) denote the number of elements whose orders
divide d. Clearly we have,
Möbius inversion now
yields
where
is defined to be 0, unless n/d
is a product of k distinct primes, in which case it equals (-1)k.
Frobenius' Theorem informs us that h(d)=m is a multiple of d.
We thus conclude as follows:
* If n divides the order of a group, then the number of elements of
order exactly n is equal to
. Here the sum is over only
those divisors d of n with the property that n/d is a product of
any number (k, say) of
distinct primes. Furthermore, m is the number of elements whose
orders divide d.